Open main menu

Changes

39 bytes removed ,  03:38, 24 January 2017
no edit summary
|DOD Approximate=No
|Summary='''Rene Descartes''' (1596-1650) was French mathematician and philosopher. Because he rejected the Aristotelian-scholastic world view embraced for most of the previous two thousand years, and laid down new foundations for knowledge, he is widely regarded as the founder of modern philosophy. [[CiteRef::Russell (1945)|p.524]][[CiteRef::Newman (2016)]][[CiteRef::Garber (1993)]] He put forward this new approach to knowledge in his ''Discourse on the Method of Rightly Conducting One’s Reason and of Seeking Truth in the Sciences'' (''Discourse on Method''), first published in 1637[[CiteRef::Descartes (2007)]]. Descartes posited a scientific methodology whereby a proposition is acceptable only if it can be clearly and distinctly perceived by the intellect beyond all reasonable doubt or follows deductively from such propositions.[[CiteRef:: Newman (2016)]] Rejecting the Aristotelian world of forms, substances, and teleology, he posited a mechanical world in which matter possessed only spatial extension and interacted only by contact. This allowed him to advance a mathematical a priorist approach to scientific knowledge and inquiry.[[CiteRef::Garber (1992)]][[CiteRef::Clarke (1992)]]
|Historical Context=The mosaic of the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries was based primarily on the works of Aristotle and some later Hellenistic natural philosophers, reconciled in various ways with Christian theology by scholars in the High Middle Ages. It included elements such as Christian theology, humoral physiology, astrology, Ptolemaic astronomy, and Christian (Catholic, in many but not all communities contemporaneous with Descartes) theology.[[CiteRef::Haldane (1905)]] The Aristotelian-Scholastic tradition formed the its centerpiece of the early seventeenth century mosaic. Descartes was well educated in this tradition when he attended the prestigious Jesuit La Fleche College between the ages of ten and eighteen. There he studied a traditional Scholastic curriculum of logic, grammar, philosophy, mathematics, and theology under Jesuit instruction. The primary goal of Jesuit education was to renew Catholic Christian faith and to combat heresy. [[CiteRef::Gaukroger (1995)|p. 38-61]] The mosaic of the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries was based primarily on the works of Aristotle and some later Hellenistic natural philosophers, reconciled in various ways with Christian theology by scholars in the high middle ages. It included elements such as Christian theology, humoral physiology, astrology, Ptolemean astronomy, and Christian (Catholic, in many but not all communities contemporaneous with Descartes) theology.[[CiteRef::Haldane (1905)]]
Notably, Descartes’ major writings are either contemporaneous with or shortly successive to periods of significant social and intellectual upheaval in Europe. Descartes was a participant in the Thirty Years War before writing his major works and traveled extensively around Europe at a time when the continent was embroiled in both reformation and counter-reformation, both of which were a wellspring of new thought in theology and philosophy.[[CiteRef::Cottingham (1992)]] Philosophically, Descartes was immediately preceded by Bacon, whose contributions to epistemology helped to weaken the foundations of the Scholastic-Aristotelian mosaic.[[CiteRef::Rodis-Lewis (1992)]] Scientifically, a number of new advancements had been made in optics, astronomy, and physiology during or shortly prior to Descartes’ lifetime; he commented on the trial of Galileo and was familiar with the works of Copernicus and Kepler, the latter of whose work was already celebrated at La Fleche College when Descartes was attending.[[CiteRef::Hatfield (2016)]] Although Descartes was critical of Galileo’s methodology it is clear that he nevertheless had read and was familiar with his work, which was instrumental in weakening the various communities’ confidence in the salience of the Aristotelian mosaic.[[CiteRef::Ariew (1986)]] Also notable is that Descartes’ most prominent teacher was the Calvinist natural philosopher Isaac Beeckman, whose work directly conflicted with the Aristotelian tradition by positing atomism and by rejecting plenism.[[CiteRef::Rodis-Lewis (1992)]] These and other factors place Descartes in a historical context rife with revolutionary change and immense scholarly interest in the changing landscape of academic inquiry.
2,020

edits