Changes

Jump to navigation Jump to search
192 bytes removed ,  03:15, 28 July 2017
no edit summary
Newton's two most important works of natural philosophy were the ''Principia'', published in 1687, which dealt with his theories of motion and universal gravitation, and ''Opticks: or, A Treatise of the Reflexions, Refractions, Inflexions, and Colours of Light'', or simply ''Opticks'', which was published in 1704 and dealt with his theories of light and color. [[CiteRef::Westfall(1999)]] More than Descartes, Newton made mathematics central to the conduct of natural philosophy, by producing a general mathematical theory of the motion of bodies. [[CiteRef::Janiak (2016)]] He posited three mathematical '''laws of motion''', together with a '''law of universal gravitation'''. Changes in the state of motion of objects were caused by '''forces''' acting on them. Quantities of force and amounts of matter were measurable. The laws specified the mathematical relationship between the acceleration experienced by an object, the quantity of matter composing it, and the magnitude of the forces acting on it. [[CiteRef::Smith (2009)]]
In contrast with the Cartesian mechanical philosophy, in Newton’s physics, material objects were not required to be in direct contact in order to influence each other's motion. Instead,forces could act at a distance. To explain both falling bodies and the motions of the moon and planets, Newton posited a '''gravitational force''' that acted as the inverse square of the distance between objects. He claimed to have derived this relationship from Kepler's observational laws of planetary motion. But, he was unable to supply a mechanical explanation for how gravity worked. Newton wrote that "I have not yet been able to deduce from phenomena the reason for these properties of gravity, and I do not feign hypotheses". [[CiteRef::Smith (2009)|p. 7]] The mathematical language used in The the ''Principia'' was geometry, which was also the basis for prior major models in celestial mechanics, including the works of Ptolemy, Copernicus and Kepler. None of these earlier works however, offered any rigorously mathematical explanation of the motions they described. [[CiteRef::Smith (2009)]]
Even though Newton presented his arguments in the ''Principia'' using the language of geometry, in the course of his work on forces and motion he invented '''integral and differential calculus'''. Although Newton circulated manuscripts, he did not actually publish his work on calculus until the first decade of the eighteenth century. [[CiteRef::Cohen and Smith (Eds.) (2002)| p. 20]] He is co-credited independently for the calculus alongside his contemporary and rival natural philosopher, Leibniz.[[CiteRef::Cohen and Smith (Eds.) (2002)|pp. 13-14]] As a mathematical technique, calculus was the first method capable of articulating the quantity of accelerationdealing with constantly changing quantities, unlocking a new world of calculations which geometry alone had been incapable of solving.[[CiteRef::Friedman (2002)]] Eventually, in the 18th century , mathematicians Jacob Hermann and Leonhard Euler expressed Newton’s laws of motion using Newton's own technique of calculus, but using and the symbolic expressions that Leibniz had developed.[[CiteRef::Smith (2009)|p. 29]] In following years, calculus became indispensable tool for scientists in the Newtonian mosaic to solve problems in physics, and to predict the behaviour of material objects with an unprecedented degree of accuracy.[[CiteRef::Smith (2009)]] Although geometry is still taught in schools today, calculus is the primary mathematical technique learned and used in physics and engineering classrooms.
=== Newton on Methodology ===
# In experimental philosophy, propositions gathered from phenomena by induction should be considered either exactly or very nearly true notwithstanding any contrary hypothesis, until yet other phenomena make such propositions either more exact or liable to exceptions.[[CiteRef::Newton (1999)|pp. 794-796]]</blockquote>
Out of these four rules a new, engaged method for conducting science emerged that stood in stark contrast to the previous passive and theoretical Cartesian and Aristotelian-scholastic methods. Propositions formulated based on observations of the natural world and placed back into the natural world to be tested empirically.[[CiteRef::Smith (2002)]] The calculus became deeply incorporated in into the experimental method, as it was used to mathematically calculate empirical predictions from natural laws, and then evaluate how exactly the prediction matched the observed reality. Newton claimed to have derived his law of universal gravitation using this method as applied to Kepler's laws of planetary motion. In the Cartesian natural philosophy, the centripetal force had already been defined as the agent that pulled the moon towards the Earth, keeping its orbit circular rather than linear. Newton appealed to rules 1) and 2) to claim that the centripetal force, and the force that compelled objects to move downwards towards the Earth, were merely two different expressions of the same thing. Newton then went on to apply the third rule, and argue that this force, which he called gravity, must be a universal property of all material objects. From here, he went on to argue for the unification of superlunary and sublunary phenomena.[[CiteRef::Harper (2002)|pp. 183-184]]
Historical research indicates that the scientific community did not use Newton's own criteria in evaluating his work. Newton's theories did not become accepted outside of England until after its prediction of the oblate spheroid shape of the Earth was confirmed by expeditions to Lapland and Peru. Newton's theories became accepted via a hypothetico-deductive method based on confirmed novel predictions that distinguished it from the rival Cartesian vortices, rather than via Newton's own inductive methodology. [[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 48-49]][[CiteRef::Terrall (1992)]][[CiteRef::McMullin (2001)]] According to McMullin, Newton's methodology ran contrary to the consensus that had been emerging among natural philosophers of his time, in favor of hypothesis. [[CiteRef::McMullin (2001)]] Christiaan Huygens and John Locke are known to have taken the experimental philosophy, if not necessarily the full content of Newton’s theories, to heart.[[CiteRef::Janiak (2016)]]
|Criticism=Although many natural philosophers in the 17th century were convinced by Newton’s views on the the proper method To proponents of conducting science, many were not willing to abandon the Cartesian mechanical philosophy, it was important that all motion in the universe be given a cause involving direct physical contact.  Contemporary philosopher Leibniz in particular was concerned that the theory of gravity as a regression in natural philosophy, as Newton could not account for the source of gravity. To the Cartesians, it was more important that all motion in the universe could be given a direct cause, which was only possible under the mechanical philosophy, even if this amounted to a larger gap between theory and experimental evidence.[[CiteRef::Janiak (2016)]]Although many natural philosophers in the 17th century were convinced by Newton’s views on the the proper method of conducting science, many were not willing to abandon the Cartesian mechanical philosophy.
|Related Topics=Methodology,
|Page Status=Needs Editing
}}
2,020

edits

Navigation menu