Changes

Jump to navigation Jump to search
4,924 bytes added ,  18:45, 9 January 2023
no edit summary
{{Definitional Topic|Singular Capitalized=Method|Plural Capitalized=Methods|Singular Lowercase=method|Plural Lowercase=methods|Indefinite Article=a|Question=What is '''Methodmethod'''? How should it be ''defined'' ?|Description=One of the tasks of scientonomy is to explain how methods change through time. Thus, a set proper definition of criteria for employment ''method'' is in theory assessmentorder.|Authors List=Hakob Barseghyan|Formulated Year=2015|Prehistory=In classical philosophy of science, although theories and methods are closely bound up with one another, theories change but the scientific method does not. Three different types According to [[Paul Hoyningen-Huene|Hoyningen-Huene]],[[CiteRef::Hoyningen-Huene (2008)]][[CiteRef::Hoyningen-Huene (2013)]] from the time of the Ancients until the second half of criteria have been the 20th century science just was characterized by its method. [[Aristotle]] and his medieval successors identified so farscience with absolute certainty guaranteed by axiomatic proof. In the Prior and Posterior Analytics as well as the Organon, Aristotle identified three determinants of scientific method: criteria the aims of discovery/ordering/display of facts gained through passive observation, the nature of demarcationthe knowledge pursued as well as the explanatory causes of that kind of knowledge, and a logical system to aid the proper arrangement of and inferences from observation.[[CiteRef::Andersen and Hepburn (2015)]] In the West, these ideas were perpetuated and refined by medieval thinkers like [[Albertus Magnus]], [[Thomas Aquinas]], [[Robert Grosseteste]], [[Roger Bacon]], criteria [[William of acceptanceOckham]], [[Andreas Vesalius]], and criteria [[Giacomo Zabarella]]. They developed accounts of the acquisition of knowledge through observation and induction and rules for the justification and application of compatibilityinduction. Methods should not be confused with openly professed Scholars from the East such as [[Al-Kindi]], [[Alhazen]], and [[Methodology|methodologiesAverroes]]were more critical of the Ancients. The Scientific Revolution of the 16th, which prescribe how science ''ought'' to be done17th, and 18th centuries involved serious reflection on the legitimacy of the methods that facilitated the rapid advancements in scientific knowledge at the time. Thinkers like [[Galileo Galilei]] and [[Francis Bacon]] emphasized mathematical description and mechanical explanation as important constituents of a disinterested method. Methods should [[Isaac Newton]]’s Opticks (1704)[[CiteRef::Newton (1704)]] and Principia Mathematica (1726)[[CiteRef::Newton (1999)]] also be differentiated excluded non-epistemic values and subjectivity from research techniquesscientific practice through his implicit method of experiments and reasoning and his explicit methodological rules. Subsequent thinkers clarified and reinforced Newton’s approach, including [[Colin Maclaurin]], which are used [[Denis Diderot]], and [[Francesco Algarotti]]. However, some criticized the self-effacement of the scientist and inductivism. These thinkers include the likes of [[George Berkeley]] (1734),[[CiteRef::Berkeley (1992)]] who challenged the Newtonian image of science, and [[David Hume]]’s attack on induction (1739).[[CiteRef::Hume (2000)]] A search for new foundations to undergird the empirical method ensued in response to these critics. The most notable example is [[Immanuel Kant]]’s (1781) reply to Hume in the Critique of Pure Reason.[[CiteRef::Kant (1781)]] Kant’s contributions generated additional debates on science and methods. In centre stage during the 19th century was [[John S. Mill]]’s inductivism versus [[William Whewell]]’s hypothetico-deductivism. For both thinkers, theory construction acceptance and data gatheringmethod employment remained closely bound up.
== Prehistory ==<div class="mw-collapsible mw-collapsed">Prehistory here </div>But the quantum revolution of the 20th century soon uprooted the security of commonsense intuitions, coaxing a renewed empiricism. From this emerged a methodological distinction by [[Hans Reichenbach]] (1938) between the contexts of discovery and justification.[[CiteRef::Reichenbach (1938)]] The literature focused on the latter, especially through such works as [[Rudolf Carnap]]’s logical positivism which attempted to axiomatize scientific theories.
== History ==Nevertheless, the distinction between the contexts of discovery and justification was challenged by the theory-ladenness of observation. Emphasis on the sociological, institutional, material, and political variables within science grew, thanks to the work of pioneers like [[Thomas Kuhn]], [[Paul Feyerabend]], [[Imre Lakatos]], [[Dudley Shapere]], [[Larry Laudan]], and [[Ernan McMullin]]. They replaced the positivists’ rational image of science with historicism. Some sociologists went further, claiming that it was not methods but social ideologies or individual interactions/circumstances that primarily determined the beliefs that obtained to scientific knowledge (e.g., Latour and Woolgar (1979),[[CiteRef::Latour and Woolgar (1979)]] (1986),[[CiteRef::Latour and Woolgar (1986)]] Shapin and Schaffer (1985)[[CiteRef::Shapin and Schaffer (1985)]]). In addition, philosophers of science increasingly specialized on specific fields within science.[[CiteRef::Andersen and Hepburn (2015)]] Combined, these changes culminated in the abandonment of a grand unifying scientific methodology. Furthermore, by the 1980s philosophers of science concluded that theories and methods change and, moreover, theories shape methods.
== Current View ==Method is currently defined as a set of criteria for employment But philosophers like Larry Laudan rejected the notion that change in theory assessmentscience occurs all at once. These criteria Instead, he proposed that theories and methodologies can be change at different times. Contemporary studies attempt to reconcile sociological and rationalist accounts of three basic types: criteria of demarcationscientific knowledge and method to understand how methods change, criteria of especially in relation to theory acceptance, and criteria of compatibility.  <imagemap>Image: Method_and_Types_of_Criteria_Class_Diagram|History=The original definition of the term was proposed by Barseghyan in 2015.png|center|627pxrect 674 251 706 289 [[WikipediaCiteRef::Object_composition#Composition|This is a symbol Barseghyan (2015)]] When the ontology of composition. It shows that scientific change was redrafted in 2019, the original definition was replaced by a method can consist of criteria of three different types[[Method (Barseghyan-2018)|new definition]].[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2018)]]desc none|Current View=</imagemap> |Related Topics=Scientific Mosaic, Theory|Page Status=Needs Editing=== Criteria of Demarcation ==|Editor Notes=}}=== Criteria of {{Acceptance ===Record ==|Community= Criteria of Compatibility === ''TODOCommunity: compatibility <> consistency''Scientonomy|Accepted From Era=CE|Accepted From Year=2016|Accepted From Month=January|Accepted From Day= Method vs. Methodology ==1|Accepted From Approximate=No <imagemap>Image:Method_and_Methodology_Definitions.png|center|441pxrect 4 3 445 249 Acceptance Indicators=That's when the first scientonomic definition of the term, [[Method(Barseghyan-2015)]], became accepted, which is a indication that the topic itself is considered legitimate.rect 536 3 980 249 [[Methodology]]|Still Accepted=Yesdesc none|Accepted Until Era=</imagemap>|Accepted Until Year=|Accepted Until Month==== Method vs. Research Technique ==|Accepted Until Day== Open Questions =|Accepted Until Approximate= No • Question 1 • Question 2 == Related Articles =|Rejection Indicators=  [[Scientific Mosaic]] [[Theory]] [[The Third Law]]}}

Navigation menu