Changes

Jump to navigation Jump to search
94 bytes added ,  15:44, 15 March 2018
no edit summary
=== Philosophy of Science ===
Philosophy of science deals with a variety of epistemological, metaphysical, and ethical questions arising from scientific inquiry.[[CiteRef::Kitcher (2016)]] These include both the normative question of how one arrives at reliable scientific knowledge and the descriptive question of how scientists have done so. Philosophical works on the question of how one acquires scientific knowledge date at least to the works of [[Aristotle ]] (384-322 BCE).
As a distinct modern academic discipline, philosophy of science had its origin with the Vienna Circle in the early twentieth century.[[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)]][[CiteRef::Kitcher (2016)]] The Vienna Circle was a group of European philosophers and scientists who met at the University of Vienna during academic terms from 1924 to 1936. It was organized by philosopher and physicist Moritz Schlick, and included the philosopher and logician Rudolf Carnap, the philosopher and sociologist Otto Neurath, and many others.[[CiteRef::Uebel (2016)]] Several members were involved in the founding of The Philosophy of Science Association in 1933. The association’s journal, ‘Philosophy of Science’ published its first issue in January 1934.[[CiteRef::Douglas (2016)]] The Vienna Circle sought to reconstruct empiricism based on new developments in mathematics, logic, and physics; especially [[Albert Einstein|Albert Einstein’s ]] theory of relativity. It became the birthplace of logical empiricism.[[CiteRef::Creath (2011)]][[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)]] The members of the circle saw themselves as champions of enlightenment, reason, and democracy in a time of metaphysical philosophy, mysticism, romanticism, and nationalism that preceded the rise of Adolf Hitler to power in Germany. They saw scientific rationality as a potent force for progressive social change.[[CiteRef::Longino (2015)]][[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)]]
Logical empiricism was a loosely unified movement rather than a specific body of ideas, but a common thread of thought can nonetheless be identified. The circle sought to reject all metaphysical claims of an underlying 'hidden world' in favor of knowledge grounded in experience, and relationships specified by powerful new tools of formal logic. As Schlick put it, “what every scientist seeks, and seeks alone, are…the rules which govern the connection of experiences, and by which alone they can be predicted”.[[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)|p. 30]] They made a distinction between two sorts of statements. The first were analytic statements that are necessarily true by convention and empty of factual content. All statements of the formal sciences; mathematics, and logic, are of this sort. The second were synthetic statements whose truth must be verifiable in experience, or from which verifiable statements could be deduced. All other statements, such as those of theology, were pseudo-statements devoid of meaning. They maintained that the diverse scientific disciplines could by unified by a common vocabulary.[[CiteRef::Cat (2014)]][[CiteRef::Hanfling (2004)]] The logical empiricists believed it was possible to distinguish a context of discovery, having the do with the actual historical and psychological processes by which scientific ideas come about, and a context of justification, having to do with the logical structure of scientific claims, and how they can properly be defended and justified. They saw the interests of philosophers of science lying in the latter, ahistorical domain.[[CiteRef::Creath (2011)]][[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)]]
The interests and goals of philosophers of science changed radically in the second half of the twentieth century because of a variety of serious problems with the bold project of logical empiricism. The proliferation of successful scientific theories involving unobservable entities like subatomic particles, molecules, and genes made the logical positivists rejection of the metaphysical notion that a hidden world underlies our experience increasingly untenable. Subsequent to the publication of [[Thomas Kuhn’s Kuhn]]’s [[Kuhn (1962a)|''The Structure of Scientific Revolutions'']] in 1962, it became evident that the logic of science could not be understood independently of its history.[[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)]]
=== History of Science ===
The field of history of science attempts to provide a descriptive account of how science has developed over time. Historical works about science have been written since ancient times.[[CiteRef::Zhmud (2006)]] In modern times, the history of science was established as a distinct academic discipline in the early twentieth century with the founding of the History of Science Society in 1924. The society is the oldest and largest devoted to the discipline.[[CiteRef:: History of Science Society (2016)]] It was founded by [[George Sarton]], who also founded the field’s first journal, Isis. Sarton, trained as a chemist and mathematician, authored a three volume four thousand page history of science that covered every civilization from antiquity to the fourteenth century. Sarton defined science as the “totality of positive knowledge”, and maintained that “the history of science is the only history which can illustrate the progress of mankind. In fact, ‘progress’ has no definite and unquestionable meaning in other fields than the field of science”.[[CiteRef::Garfield (1985)]] Sarton’s ultimate goal was a philosophy of science that bridged the gap between the sciences and the humanities.
The idea that scientific development involved the continuous accumulation of positive knowledge was challenged by physicist and historian of science [[Thomas Kuhn]] in 1962 in his ''The Structure of Scientific Revolutions''.[[CiteRef::Kuhn (1962a)]] Inspired by his studies of the Copernican Revolution, and drawing primarily on examples from the physical sciences, Kuhn argued that scientific development involved revolutionary discontinuities. He spoke of scientific paradigms, which are the reigning scientific conceptual frameworks of non-revolutionary periods. Paradigms are constellations of theoretical beliefs, values, methods, and techniques shared by a scientific discipline. Normal, non-revolutionary science consists in solving problems and explaining new phenomena using the tools provided by the paradigm. A scientific revolution occurs when one paradigm is replaced by another. One groundbreaking aspect of Kuhn's work is that it greatly expanded the scope of what historians generally recognized as science. He argued that the Aristotelian framework that preceded modern science was recognizable as a reasonable scientific framework in terms of its times. Many philosophers of science, steeped in logical empiricism, found Kuhn's notion of the incommensurability of paradigms troubling. It seemed to call into question the rationality of theory choice. On the other hand, Kuhn's work tapped pre-existing philosophical interest in a more historicist and naturalistic view of scientific rationality.[[CiteRef::Golinski (2012)]] Post-Kuhnian debates led to the abandonment of the notion of a distinct context of discovery and context of justification. Social scientists saw it as grounds for positing influence by social and political factors external to science on its content. Particularist historical critics questioned the general applicability of Kuhn's ideas. Kuhn's large scale vision had limited influence on historians, who were generally moving towards more small-scale projects.[[CiteRef::Golinski (2012)]][[CiteRef::Bird (2011)]]
=== History and Philosophy of Science ===
As a joint discipline, history and philosophy of science seeks to create a historicised philosophy of science. The descriptive task of understanding scientific development and the normative task of prescribing reliable methods of seeking knowledge are often not distinguished. Academic programs in the history and philosophy of science were established at both Princeton University and Indiana University in 1960.[[CiteRef::Mauskopf and Schmaltz (2012)]] The Indiana department was founded by [[Norwood Hanson|Norwood Russell Hanson]].[[CiteRef::Hickney (2016)]] Hanson’s book ‘Patterns of Discovery’, published in 1958 [[CiteRef::Hanson (1958)]], stressed the theory-ladenness of observation and the historical nature of scientific rationality in an exploration of modern particle physics.[[CiteRef::Lund (2010)]] As a work in the history of science, Kuhn’s ‘Structure of Scientific Revolutions’ attracted considerable attention from philosophers, in part because some philosophers besides Hanson, including [[Stephen Toulmin]], had been working on rather similar ideas.[[CiteRef::Mauskopf and Schmaltz (2012)]] History and philosophy of science programs proliferated in the 1960's and 1970's, fueled in part, by interest in Kuhn's work and in part by the Cold War willingness of western governments to fund projects that promoted interest in science.[[CiteRef::Miller (2012)]] Historicist views of scientific epistemology and rationality have subsequently been dominant. Irme [[Imre Lakatos ]] presented scientific development in terms of research programs that progressed when they made successful novel predictions, and degenerated when they failed to do so, and when core assumptions were adjusted in an arbitrary manner to avoid falsification.[[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)]][[CiteRef::Lakatos (1978a)]] Empirical historical evidence led philosophers to reject the notion of a unitary scientific method that had remained fixed through history.[[CiteRef::Grobler (1990)]] Laudan’s reticulated model of scientific rationality posited during assessment of a theory, other theories, methods, and values all interact.[[CiteRef::Laudan (1984a)]] Philosopher [[Ronald Giere ]] dubbed the joining of history and philosophy of science a "marriage of convenience".[[CiteRef::Giere (2012)]] Many question whether the two have formed a genuinely unified discipline because of the diverse interests and political commitments of those who study the development of science.[[CiteRef::Golinski (1998)]]
=== Sociology of Scientific Knowledge ===
The field of sociology, the scientific study of human social structures, was founded by [[Robert Merton]]. In the 1940’s Merton began studying the sociology of scientific communities. However, his studies had little contact with epistemology or philosophy of science, except in the general sense of identifying the social conditions under which scientific inquiry is possible and fruitful. Merton assumed a view of scientific knowledge similar to that of the logical empiricists.[[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)]] The philosophers [[John Stuart Mill]], [[Charles Sanders PiercePeirce]], and [[Karl Popper ]] stressed the social dimension of scientific epistemology, but their view did not become the dominant one until after the publication of Kuhn’s ''Structure of Scientific Revolutions''.[[CiteRef::Longino (2015)]]The ‘strong program’ of the sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK) began in the 1970’s at the University of Edinburgh in Scotland, under the leadership of sociologist [[Barry Barnes ]] and philosopher [[David Bloor]]. Proponents of SSK view knowledge as a collective social product, and seek a naturalistic account of its production. In effect, they seek to use the methods of social science to study science itself.[[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)]][[CiteRef::Barnes, Bloor, and Henry (1996)]] A central principle of the ‘strong program’ is the symmetry principle, in which normative epistemological concerns are ‘screened out’ for the sake of illuminating social interactions and relationships involved in the production of knowledge. Its value is most evident when considering knowledge processes far removed from our own by time and culture, such as when understanding how western astronomy disentangled itself from astrology in seventeenth century Europe.[[CiteRef::Golinski (1998)]] Social constructivism has sometimes been criticized as an attempt to “explain away” science as nothing but social power structures.[[CiteRef::Longino (2015)]] However, recent attempts to introduce cognitive science concepts into social epistemology hold much promise of naturalizing rationality, and thereby obviating such concerns.[[CiteRef::Giere and Moffatt (2003)]][[CiteRef::Giere (2002)]]
|History=The term ''scientonomy'' was adopted to denote an empirical descriptive ''science of science'' subsequent to the publication of [[Barseghyan (2015)|''The Laws of Scientific Change'']].[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)]]
|Related Topics=Scientific Mosaic, Scientific Change, Scope of Scientonomy, Assessment of Scientonomy, Possibility of Scientonomy, Mechanism of Scientific Change, Ontology of Scientific Change,
2,020

edits

Navigation menu