Changes

Jump to navigation Jump to search
no edit summary
The same idea has been expressed around the same time by Ernan McMullin. In his account of the transition from the Aristotelian Medieval method to the hypothetico-deductive method in the early 18th century, McMullin shows that the employment of the hypothetico-deductivism was a result of accepting that the world is more complex than it appears in our observations.[[CiteRef::McMullin (1988)|pp. 32-34]]
There have been many other attempts at explaining how methods of theory evaluation come to be employed by a community. Consider, for instance the reconstructions of Plato’s method performed by David Lindberg,[[CiteRef::Lindberg (2007)|pp. 37-38]] or the proposal of synchronous change in paradigm shifts by Thomas Kuhn.[[CiteRef::Kuhn (1962)]]
[[Barry Barnes]], [[David Bloor]], [[Bruno Latour]], [[Steve Woolgar]] and other have suggested that the methods are determined to a large degree by the underlying sociocultural factors.[[CiteRef::Latour and Woolgar (1979)]][[CiteRef::Barnes, Bloor, and Henry (1996)]]
[[Paul Feyerabend]] went as far as to argue that in many cases methods are chosen in an arbitrary fashion.[[CiteRef::Feyerabend (1975a)]]
|History=In the context of scientonomy the answer to this question has been traditionally provided by [[The Third Law|the third law]]. Until 2016 it was [[The Third Law (Barseghyan-2015)|the third law]] as formulated by [[Hakob Barseghyan]].[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 54]]

Navigation menu