Changes

Jump to navigation Jump to search
no edit summary
{{Theory Example
|Title=Possible Mosaic Split: Acceptance of the Cartesian natural philosophy in Cambridge circa 1680.
|Description=Barseghyan (2015) contrasts the replacement of the Aristotelian-Medieval method with the Newtonian method in Britain and the Cartesian method in France -- a broad case which might seem like an instance of mosaic split, but is not -- with a more specific historical example of potential mosaic split. He outlines that specific historical example, ''the acceptance of the Cartesian natural philosophy in Cambridge circa 1680'', as follows:
<blockquote>Let us begin with the available historical data. Prior to the 1680s, the Aristotelian-medieval natural philosophy was taught in schools across Europe, with alternative theories included into the curricula only sporadically. If my understanding is correct, the first university where the Cartesian natural philosophy was accepted and taught on a regular basis was Cambridge. Although the theory had been sporadically taught since the 1660s, it began to be taught systematically only circa 1680.379 Thus, it is not surprising that when one Cambridge professor Isaac Newton was writing his magnum opus, the main target of his criticism was Descartes’s theory, not that of Aristotle. According to the historical data, during the last two decades of the 17th century, Cambridge remained the only university where the Cartesian theory was generally accepted. The situation changed circa 1700, when the Cartesian natural philosophy together with its respective modifications by Huygens, Malebranche and others became accepted in France380France, Holland381 Holland and Sweden382Sweden. As for Oxford, it never accepted the Cartesian theory but switched directly to the Newtonian theory circa 1690.383 In Cambridge, the transition from the Cartesian natural philosophy to that of Newton took place in the 1700s.384 Most likely, the universities of the Dutch Republic (Leiden and Utrecht) were the first on the Continent to accept the Newtonian theory by 1720.385 In France and Sweden, the Newtonian theory replaced the Cartesian natural philosophy circa 1740.386 The picture wouldn’t be complete if we didn’t mention the important theological differences: Catholic theology was accepted in Paris; Anglican theology was accepted in Oxford and Cambridge; in Holland and Sweden the accepted theology was that of Protestantism.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|pp. 211-212]]</blockquote>
[Timeline Diagram]A draft timeline of the situation, including theological differences, at the end of the 17th century has been constructed by Barseghyan:
TODO{{PrintDiagramFile|diagram file=Draft_Timeline_1680_Mosaics.png}}  Barseghyan (2015) continues as follows: Finish <blockquote> Although the diagram hardly scratches the surface of the colorful 17-18th century landscape, it points to ''at least two possible candidates of mosaic split''. Apparently, there seem to have been a split in the Anglican mosaic of Britain circa 1680, when the Cartesian natural philosophy became accepted in Cambridge, and also probably in the Protestant mosaic sometime by 1720, when the Newtonian theory became accepted in Holland.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|pp. 212]]</blockquote> Barseghyan (2015) more closely examines the first potential case: the acceptance of Cartesian natural philosophy in Cambridge: <blockquote> If my reading is correct, then this was a typical case of mosaic split: after the acceptance of the Cartesian theory, the mosaic of Cambridge became different from the Aristotelian-Anglican mosaic of other British universities. Note that this mosaic split was caused by the acceptance of only one new theory. Therefore, it could only be a result of an inconclusive theory assessment. At this point, we can only hypothesize as to why exactly the outcome of the assessment of the Cartesian theory was inconclusive. My historical hypothesis is that it had to do with the inconclusiveness of the Aristotelian-medieval method employed at the time, i.e. with the vagueness of the implicit expectations of the community of the time.  It is easily seen that the then-employed Aristotelian-medieval method allowed for two distinct scenarios of theory assessment. On the one hand, if a proposition was meant as a theorem, it was only expected to show that it did in fact follow from other accepted propositions. That much would be sufficient for a new theorem to become accepted. This part of the method is straightforward – no ambiguity here. If, on the other hand, a proposition was not meant as a theorem – if it was supposed to be a separate axiom – then it was expected to be intuitively true. But what does it mean to be intuitively true? Nowadays we seem to realize that no proposition can be intuitively true (unless of course it is a tautology) and that intuition, even when “schooled by experience”, is not the best advisor in theory assessment.66 Therefore, a theory could merely appear intuitively true to the community of the time. This was the actual expectation of the scientific community in the 17th century – the appearance of intuitive truth. One indication of this is the fact that both Descartes and Newton understood the vital necessity of presenting their systems in the axiomatic-deductive form. They also made all possible efforts to show that their axioms – the starting points of their deductions – were beyond any reasonable doubt. They both realized that if their theories are ever to be accepted, their axioms must appear clear to anyone who is knowledgeable enough to understand them. But this is exactly what was expected by the scientific community of the time. Yet, the requirement of intuitive truth is extremely vague: what appears intuitively true to me need not necessarily appear intuitively true to others.  I think this can explain why the mosaic split of the 1680s took place. The axioms of the Cartesian natural philosophy were meant as self-evident intuitively true propositions. But as with any “intuitive truth”, scientists could easily disagree as to whether the axioms were indeed intuitively true. As a result, the outcome of the assessment of the Cartesian theory was “inconclusive”. In that situation, a mosaic split was one of the possible courses of events (by the possible mosaic split theorem). Of course the mosaic split wasn’t inevitable – it was merely one of the possibilities which actualized. This Aristotelian “bring before me intuitive true propositions” requirement was so vague that theory assessment could easily yield an “inconclusive” outcome and, consequently, result in a mosaic split. It is not surprising, therefore, that the British mosaic did actually split in the 1680s when the Cartesian natural philosophy was accepted only in Cambridge. This was an instance of ''possible mosaic split''.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|pp. 212-213]]</blockquote>
|Example Type=Historical
}}

Navigation menu