Changes

Jump to navigation Jump to search
no edit summary
{{Theory
|Topic=Mechanism of Method Employment
|Theory Type=Descriptive
|Subject=
|Predicate=
|Title=The Third Law
|Theory Type=Descriptive
|Alternate Titles=the law of method employment
|Title Formula=
|Text Formula=
|Formulation Text=A method becomes employed only when it is deducible from other employed methods and accepted theories of the time.
|Formulation FileObject=The Third Law Barseghyan 2015.png|Topic=Mechanism of Method Employment
|Authors List=Hakob Barseghyan,
|Formulated Year=2015
|Formulation File=The Third Law Barseghyan 2015.png|Description=Barseghyan's formulation of the third law states that a [[Method|method]] becomes [[Employed Method|employed]] only when it is deducible from other employed methods and accepted [[Theory|theories]] of the time."Essentially," Barseghyan writes, "the third law stipulates that our accepted theories shape our employed methods".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 132]]
According to this formulation, a method becomes employed when:
In practice, the third law states that when a new phenomenon is discovered, this discovery produces an abstract requirement to take that discovery into account when testing relevant theories. This abstract requirement is then specified by a new employed method.
The third law does not stipulate how methods should go about specifying any new abstract requirement. The third law functions as a descriptive account of how methods change, and is not responsible for describing how methods ought to change. As such, it is an effective means of explicating the requirements of other employed methods. The third law has an important corollary: scientific change is not necessarily a ''synchronous '' process, which notably differs from Kuhn's view of scientific change as a ''wholesale,'' ''synchronous'' process.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 151]] This corollary is known as the [[Asynchronism of Method Employment theorem (Barseghyan-2015)]].|Resource=Barseghyan (2015)|Prehistory=The basic idea of ''the third law'' is not new. A number of philosophers have suggested that our beliefs about the world shape how we engage with the world. Different versions of this idea can be found in the works of [[Thomas Kuhn]], [[Paul Feyerabend]], [[Dudley Shapere]], [[Larry Laudan]], and [[Ernan McMullin]]. Most noteworthy is [[Larry Laudan]]’s account of changes in drug trial methods. In his ''Science and Values'', Laudan argued that the discovery of previously unaccounted effects resulted in the formulation of new methods of drug testing.[[CiteRef::Laudan (1984a)|pp. 38-39]] However, while Laudan’s account hints at aspects of ''the third law'', it ultimately conflates [[Method|methods]] and [[Methodology|methodologies]].[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|pp. 130-131]] [[Ernan McMullin]]’s accounts of historical methods offer another example of a prototype of ''the third law''. McMullin showed how the hypothetico-deductive method came to replace the Aristotelian Medieval method in the 18th century. In his account, McMullin shows that the employment of the hypothetico-deductivism was a result of accepting that the world is more complex than it appears in our observations.[[CiteRef::McMullin (1988)|p. 32-34]] These accounts demonstrate how our accepted theories impact our criteria of theory assessment. There have been many other attempts at explicating the way in which methods change, such as the reconstructions of Plato’s method performed by [[David Lindberg]], or the proposal of synchronous change in paradigm shifts by [[Thomas Kuhn]]. Nevertheless, according to Barseghyan, "what we have had so far is a picture from a bird’s eye perspective. What we lack is the knowledge of the actual mechanism: how exactly can accepted theories shape employed methods?".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 133]]|History=Barseghyan's formulation of the third law was the first attempt to address the problem of method employment in the scientonomic context.|Page Status=Editor Approved|Editor Notes=Great job, Izzy!}}{{YouTube Video|VideoID=BBBxJ8yYrsg|VideoStartAt=253|VideoDescription=The third law explained by Hakob Barseghyan|VideoEmbedSection=Description}}{{Theory Example|Title=Drug Trial Methods|Description="How exactly can changes in accepted theories trigger changes in employed methods? What is the precise mechanism of method change? How do methods become employed?".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 136]] Barseghyan presents the example of testing a new drug for alleviating depression to as an example of the third law and in answer to these questions. In summary, the evolution of the drug trial methods is an example of the third law in action. For example, the discovery of the placebo effect in drug testing demonstrates that fake treatment can cause improvement in patient symptoms. As a result of its discovery the abstract requirement of “when assessing a drug’s efficacy, the possible placebo effect must be taken into account” was generated. This abstract requirement is, by definition, an accepted theory which stipulates that, if ignored, substantial doubt would be cast on any trial. As a result of this new theory, the Single-Blind Trial method was devised. The currently employed method in drug testing is the Double-Blind Trial, a method which specifies all of the abstract requirements of its predecessors. It is an apt illustration of how new methods are generated through the acceptance of new theories, as well as how new methods employ the abstract requirements of their predecessors.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|pp. 132-152]] Specifically, Barseghyan begins with the question "How can we ensure that the improvement was due to the drug itself and not due to other unaccounted factors?" The question is answered by the implementation of a ''controlled trial'', wherein "we organize a trial with two groups of patients with the same condition – the active group and the control group. Only the patients in the active group receive the drug".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 134]]<blockquote>What we have here is a transition from one method to another triggered by a new piece of knowledge about the world. The initial method was something along the lines of hypothetico-deductivism: we had a hypothesis “the drug is effective in alleviating depression” and we wanted to confirm it experimentally. Once we learnt that the alleviation may be due to other factors, our initial method was modified to require that a drug’s efficacy must be tested in a controlled trial.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 134]]</blockquote>
{{#evtAnother transition in method occurred when upon the discovery of the ''placebo effect'', or the fact "that the improvement in patients’ condition can be due to the patients’ belief that the treatment will improve their condition".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 135]] Now,<blockquote>it was no longer sufficient to have two groups of patients. If only one of the two groups received the drug then the resulting positive effect could be due to the patients’ belief that the drug was really efficient in alleviating their condition. The solution was to organize a ''blind trial.'' We take two groups of patients with the condition, but this time we make sure that both groups of patients believe that they undergo treatment. However, only the patients of the active group receive the real drug; to the patients in the control group we give a placebo (fake treatment).[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 135]]</blockquote>Once again, Barseghyan writes, "this is an instance of a method change brought about by a change in accepted theories".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 135]] service=youtube<blockquote>But why are we forced to introduce this new requirement to our method of drug testing? Well, because this new requirement follows deductively from two elements of the mosaic – from our knowledge that the results of testing a hypothesis about a drug’s efficacy may be voided by the placebo effect and from a more fundamental requirement that we must accept only the best available hypotheses.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|id=BBBxJ8yYrsgp. 137]]</blockquote> Notably, "while the new requirement is abstract (“the possible placebo effect must be taken into account”), the blind trial method is concrete, for it prescribes how exactly the testing should be done. Thus, ''the blind trial method'' specifies the new abstract requirement. This is the relation of ''implementation'': a more concrete method implements the requirements of a more abstract method by making them more concrete".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|urlargs=start=253p. 138]] That is, ''the blind trial method'' is not the only possible ''implementation'' of the abstract requirement to take the placebo effect into account.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 138]] In Barseghyan's words, "the same abstract requirement can have many different implementations".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 139]]  A final change in method occurred when ''experimenter's bias'' was discovered:<blockquote>The researchers that are in contact with patients can give patients conscious or unconscious hints as to which group is which. It is possible that the positive effect of the drug established in a blind trial was due to the fact that the patients in the placebo group knew that they were given a placebo. The method of drug testing was modified yet again to reflect this newly discovered phenomenon. The contemporary approach is to perform a double-blind trial where neither patients nor researchers know which group is which.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|alignment=rightpp. 135-136]]</blockquote>  {{PrintDiagramFile|descriptiondiagram file=Double Blind Trial Deduction (Barseghyan-2015-139).png}}  The third law explained by Hakob Barseghyan''double-blind trial method'' is a further example of the relation of ''implementation''.|containerExample Type=frame Historical
}}
{{Theory Example
|Title=The Double-Blind Trial Method (Two Scenarios for Method Employment)
|Description=As Barseghyan explains, ''the double-blind trial method'' "is based on our belief that by performing a double-blind trial we forestall the chance of unaccounted effects, placebo effect, and experimenter’s bias".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 141]]
The third law does not stipulate how methods should go about specifying any new abstract requirement. The third law functions as propositions that this premise is based on in turn derive from theories that are acecpted; for example, "our belief that a descriptive account trial with two similar groups minimizes the chance of how methods changeunaccounted effects follows from our knowledge about statistical regularities, and is not responsible for describing how methods ought i.e. from our belief that two statistically similar groups can be expected to changebehave similarly ''ceteris paribus''".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. As such142]] Similarly, it is an effective means our knowledge of explicating physiology and psychology lead to our understanding that we can void the requirements placebo effect with fake pills.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 142]] Our knowledge of psychology allows us to understand that researchers can bias patients from their own knowledge of other employed methodswhich group is which.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. The Aristotelian142]] Clearly, these premises, although trivial, are currently accepted within our scientific mosaic.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 142]] Hence, the ''double-Medieval blind trial method '', although an ''implementation'' of abstract requirements, is one such example still based on our currently accepted theories. This is true in all scenarios of its utility''implementation''.[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p.142]]
Thus, methods follow deductively from elements of the mosaic whether they follow strictly from theories and methods or implement abstract requirements. This is an important similarity between the two scenarios for method employment.|Example Type=Historical}}{{Theory Example|Title=Aristotelian-Medieval Method|Description=In Barseghyan’s explication of the Aristotelian-Medieval method, he illustrates how Aristotelian natural philosophy impacted the method of the time. [[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 143]] Most notable is the acceptance of teleology – a theory which states that every thing has a nature it seeks to fulfill (e.g. an acorn’s nature is to become an oak tree). It stood to reason that The best theories, then, would uncover the nature of a thing can . If only be intuitively grasped by an experienced person. This fundamental belief generated a method which specifies these requirements known as the Aristotelian-Medieval methodbest theories are acceptable, and this leads to the abstract requirement that "A theory is an illustration of how employed methods are deductive consequences of acceptable only if it grasps the accepted theories nature of the timea thing".
The third law has also proven useful in explicating such requirements as Confirmed Novel Predictions (CNP). According It stood to reason that the hypothetico-deductive method, nature of a theory which challenges our accepted ontology must provide CNP in order to become acceptedthing can only be intuitively grasped by an experienced person. HoweverThis fundamental belief, combined with the history of CNP has been abstract requirement outline above, led to a point of confusion for some time. By method which specifies these requirements known as the Third Law, one can show that Aristotelian-Medieval method: "A proposition is acceptable if it grasps the requirement of CNP has not always been expected nature of new theories. When Newton published his Principia, CNP were not a requirement of his professed methodthing through intuition schooled by experience, yet they were still providedor if it is deduced from general intuitive propositions". On the other hand, Clark’s law of diminishing returns had no such predictions[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 145]] This is because Newton’s proposal an illustration of how employed methods are deductive consequences of unobservable entities, such as gravity and absolute space, challenged the accepted ontology theories of the time, while Clark’s simply accounted for the data already available. Thus, in utilizing the Third Law, one can discover both when certain criteria become an implicit rule and under what conditions they are necessary.|ResourceExample Type=Historical}}{{Theory Example|Title=Barseghyan (2015)Confirmed Novel Predictions|PrehistoryDescription=The basic idea of ''the third law'' is not newhas also proven useful in explicating such requirements as Confirmed Novel Predictions (CNP). A number of philosophers have suggested that our beliefs about the world shape how we engage with the world. Different versions of this idea can be found in the works of [[Thomas KuhnCiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|pp. 146-150]], [[Paul Feyerabend]], [[Dudley Shapere]], [[Larry Laudan]], and [[Ernan McMullin]].
Most noteworthy According to the hypothetico-deductive method, a theory which challenges our accepted ontology must provide CNP in order to become accepted. However, the history of CNP has been a point of confusion for some time. By the Third Law, one can show that the requirement of CNP has not always been expected of new theories. When Newton published his Principia (~1740), CNP were not a requirement of his professed method, yet they were still provided. This is also true in the cases of Fresnel's wave theory of light (~1820), Einstein's general relativity (~1920), continental drift theory (1960s), and electroweak unification (1970s).[[Larry LaudanCiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 146]]’s account  On the other hand, Clark’s law of changes diminishing returns (1900) had no such predictions. They also played no role in the acceptance of Mayer's lunar theory (1760s), Coulomb's inverse square law (early 1800s), the three laws of thermodynamics (1850s), and quantum mechanics (1927).[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. 146]] Barseghyan explains that this indicates that is because "we do expect confirmed novel predictions but only in drug trial methodsvery special circumstances. There was one common characteristic in all those episodes… they all altered our views on the structural elements of the world".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|p. In his 146]] For instance, in our key examples, Newton’s proposal of unobservable entities, such as gravity and absolute space, challenged the ''Science and Valuesaccepted ontology''of the time, Laudan argued while Clark’s simply accounted for the data already available.  Barseghyan presents his historical hypothesis that this specific requirement for CNP has been employed in natural science since the 18th century. Assuming he is correct (for the discovery sake of previously unaccounted effects resulted in argument), he continues: "The ''third law'' stipulates that the formulation requirement of confirmed novel predictions could become employed only if it was a deductive consequence of new the accepted theories and other employed methods of drug testingthe time. So a question arises: what theories and methods does this requirement follow from?".[[CiteRef::Laudan Barseghyan (19842015)|pp. 38147-39148]] However Barseghyan answers the question with two principles. For one, there is a principle, while Laudan’s account hints at aspects of ''implicit in our contemporary mosaic and accepted since the third law''eighteenth century, that states: "the world is more complex than it ultimately conflates appears in observations, that there is more to the world than meets the eye".[[MethodCiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|methodsp. 148]] and Thus, observations may not tell the whole story, as what we observe may an effect of an unobservable. Secondly, "it has been accepted since the early eighteenth century that, in principle, any phenomenon can be produced by an infinite number of different underlying mechanisms".[[MethodologyCiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|methodologiesp. 148]]"This leads us to the thesis of underdetermination that, in principle, any finite body of evidence can be explained in an infinite number of ways".[[CiteRef::Barseghyan (2015)|ppp. 130-131148]]Therefore:
Ernan McMullin’s accounts of historical methods offer another example of <blockquote> The abstract requirement that follows from these two principles is that whenever we assess a prototype theory that introduces some new internal mechanisms (new types of sub-stances, particles, forces, fields, interaction, processes etc.) we must take into account that this hypothesized internal mechanism may turn out to be fictitious even if it manages to predict the known phenomena with utmost precision. In other words, we ddo not tolerate "fiddling" with the ''the third lawaccepted ontology;''. McMullin showed how the implicit method used by Galileo was at odds with if a theory attemptes to modify the method he professed to use and accepted ontology, it must show that which was actually employed at the timeit is not cooked-up.[[CiteRef::Allen Barseghyan (19882015)|p. 148]] </blockquote>
FurthermoreThis abstract requirement can then be implemented in several ways, McMullin showed how the hypothetico-deductive method came to replace the Aristotelian Medieval method in the 18th centuryincluding through our contemporary requirement of ''confirmed novel predictions''. In his account, McMullin shows that the employment This is an illustration of the hypothetico-deductivism was a result second scenario of accepting that the world is more complex than it appears in our observations.[[CiteRef::McMullin (1988)|pp. 32-34.]] These accounts demonstrate how our accepted theories impact our implicit requirements for investigating the worldmethod employment.
There have been many other attempts at explicating the way Thus, in which methods change, such as utilizing the reconstructions of Plato’s method performed by David Lindbergthird law, or the proposal of synchronous change in paradigm shifts by Thomas Kuhnone can discover both when certain criteria become an implicit rule and under what conditions they are necessary.|HistoryExample Type=Barseghyan's formulation of the third law was the first attempt to address the problem of method employment in the scientonomic context.Historical
}}
{{Acceptance Record
|Accepted From Day=1
|Accepted From Approximate=Yes
|Acceptance Indicators=The law became ''de facto'' accepted by the community at that time together with the whole [[The Theory of Scientific Change|theory of scientific change]]. Since then, [[Modification:Sciento-2016-0001|attempts]] have been made to replace this law,[[CiteRef::Sebastien (2016)]] which is a very good indicator of theory acceptance.
|Still Accepted=No
|Accepted Until Era=CE

Navigation menu